MUST WE ALWAYS USE CPR?
Leslie J. Blackhall, M.D.
 

 

New England Journal of Medicine, “Sounding Board”
Nov. 12, 1987; vol. 317, No. 20, pp. 1281-1285  
MS-Word Doc    PDF Doc


CARDIOPULMONARY resuscitation (CPR) as we know it today came into being after the invention of closed-chest cardiac massage in 1960.1 This technique was originally developed for victims of sudden cardiac or respiratory arrest. As the introduction to one monograph on CPR, written in 1965, says, “The techniques described in this monograph are designed to resuscitate the victim of acute insult, whether it be from[:]

[1] drowning,
[2] electrical shock,
[3] untoward effect of drugs,
[4] anesthetic accident,
[5] heart block,
[6] acute MI [myocardial infarction] or
[7] surgery.” 2

At present, however, it is standard practice to attempt CPR on any patient in the hospital who has a cardiac arrest, regardless of the underlying illness. The exceptions, of course, are patients who request not to receive such treatment. The rights of patients to refuse this intervention have been well delineated in the courts, yet despite 27 years of experience with CPR and approximately 10 years of experience with “do-not-resuscitate” (DNR) protocols, many questions concerning CPR remain, including who should be involved in decisions about DNR orders and under what circumstances such decisions should be made. Infrequently discussed (although perhaps not infrequently encountered) is the situation in which a patient wants CPR but the physician believes that it is contraindicated. In these cases, patients almost invariably remain “full code,” and physicians feel obligated to provide a treatment that they have reason to believe will not be beneficial and may actually be harmful. Are they so obligated?

            I was recently involved in a case that illustrates this conflict. A 30-year-old woman with acute myelogenous leukemia who had relapsed from her second remission approximately one month earlier was started on an experimental chemotherapeutic regimen that left her with profound neutropenia and thrombocytopenia for almost four weeks. After four weeks, a bone marrow biopsy revealed regeneration with blasts, indicating failure of the chemotherapy. The patient also had pneumonia thought to be fungal, which was not responding to treatment with broad-spectrum antibiotics, including amphotericin. She (with her family) was asked, “If your heart or lungs stop working, do you want us to pump on your chest and put you on a breathing machine?” The patient and her family decided that she should receive a full CPR effort. The house staff and nursing staff were opposed to this decision, and much conflict ensued.

            We use CPR in the way we do for a variety of medical, historical, and psychological reasons. Although CPR was initially used selectively on patients with acute illness - mainly because those trained in its use were cardiologists, anesthesiologists, and surgeons, whose patients tended to have the reversible causes of cardiac arrest described in the quotation above - the increased training of nurses and physicians in the technique and the development of “code teams” rapidly expanded the patient population undergoing CPR. The development of code protocols in hospitals, whereby CPR was promptly begun on any patient discovered to have no pulse, extended the indications for this technique to include all patients with cardiac arrest, regardless of the underlying illness. These changes were instituted to improve the chances of a response to CPR and to ensure good neurologic function in patients who did respond. They created a problem, however, because many physicians recognized that there were some patients for whom CPR was inadvisable because of terminal illness or poor quality of life. The dilemma was how to decide when not to do CPR. After many court cases and much discussion among physicians, DNR orders were developed to encourage open discussion of these issues and to allow patient participation in the decisions. Analysis of the legal and ethical aspects of such orders has focused on the issue of patient autonomy – the right of competent patients to refuse any procedure and of incompetent patients to refuse through a surrogate. Thus, although the DNR order is written by a physician, its legitimacy comes from the patient; the order signifies that the patient has refused a procedure. The development of DNR protocols has not solved all the problems associated with CPR, however. Since CPR is performed routinely in the absence of a DNR order and because physicians frequently do not offer their patients a choice between CPR and a DNR order,3-7 the decision to perform CPR is usually made without the patient’s involvement.

            The case I described earlier, however, presents a different problem. In this case the patient and family were consulted. The problem was that their decision ran contrary to the physician’s medical judgment. The conflict that then arose was difficult to resolve, but in such cases it seems insufficient for physicians to cite patient autonomy and wash their hands of further responsibility. When a patient’s request for treatment is in conflict with a physician’s responsibility to provide what he or she believes to be good medical care, the calculation is difficult. A recent paper concerning this type of conflict concluded that there is no ethical imperative requiring physicians to perform procedures in the absence of at least a “modicum of medical benefit.”8 A review of the literature on the medical aspects of CPR, therefore, may aid us in our analysis of the ethical aspects of this case.

            Kouwenhoven et al., in a paper that first described closed-chest cardiac massage, reported a long-term survival rate of 70 percent (14 of 20 patients)1 This impressive rate has never been duplicated. In 13 papers published since 1960, the rates for survival until hospital discharge ranged from 5 to 23 percent.9–21 Most papers report a survival rate of less than 15 percent, and one of the three studies with rates higher than 15 percent excluded patients with cancer, repeated arrests, or chronic illness and total dependence - all conditions associated with poor outcome. It is clear that survival after CPR is related to the underlying illness that leads to the arrest and that patients with certain conditions very rarely survive. For example, Bedell et al., in a study of 294 consecutive patients who had cardiac arrest at the Beth Israel Hospital in Boston, found that although 44 percent initially responded to CPR, only 14 per-cent survived until discharge. No patient with metastatic cancer survived until discharge, nor did any patient with an acute stroke, sepsis, or pneumonia. Only 2 percent of patients with severe cardiomyopathy and 2 percent of patients who had had hypotension for 24 hours survived. Only 3 percent of the patients with renal failure (defined as a blood urea nitrogen level >50 mg per deciliter) survived, and no patient who required dialysis or had oliguria for 24 hours before the cardiac arrest survived until discharge.

            These dismal results only confirmed what numerous other studies had shown before - that CPR is frequently ineffective, even in patients in whom it has the best chance of succeeding: those with acute myocardial infarctions or complications due to anesthesia. It is almost never successful in patients with chronic debilitating illnesses.

            Peatfield et al. assessed the results of CPR in 1063 patients over a 10-year period. The initial response was 32.4 percent, but only 8.7 percent survived until discharge. All patients with cancer or gastrointestinal hemorrhage died. In contrast, 15 percent of patients with acute myocardial infarction who required CPR survived.” In a study by Hershy and Fisher, 14 percent of all patients undergoing CPR survived, but only 6 percent of patients on the general wards survived.12 The authors attributed this to the fact that most patients with the acute, reversible causes of cardiac arrest were in critical care units or the emergency room, whereas the patients on the general wards had the types of chronic illnesses associated with a poor outcome. No patient with cancer or an acute stroke survived CPR in their study. Similarly, a study by Johnson et al. of 552 patients showed that 32 percent were alive at 24 hours but only 14.9 percent survived until discharge. No patient with sepsis, cancer, or gastrointestinal hemorrhage survived until discharge, and only 3 percent of patients with renal failure survived.13

            In all these papers, we see a discrepancy between the initial response rate (16 to 45 percent) and survival until discharge (5 to 23 percent overall, with less than 5 percent survival in many groups). Studies that considered the length of survival of patients who were initially resuscitated but died before discharge found that these patients lived an average of 2 to 14 days, usually in an intensive care unit.”,’2,’4 The risk of the development of a chronic vegetative state after CPR was 2 percent in the paper by Johnson et al.13 and 2.7 percent in a paper by Messert and Quaglieri15 (10 percent of the patients who survived CPR in their study). Thus, although the number of patients who are in a chronic vegetative state after CPR is small, in many disease categories, it approaches the number who survive CPR.

            With the above data in mind, let us look again at the case of the young woman with leukemia unresponsive to chemotherapy, bone marrow regenerating with blasts, and lungs affected by a rapidly progressing pneumonia. Despite experimental chemotherapy and treatment with broad-spectrum antibiotics, her condition was rapidly deteriorating. From the medical perspective, was there a “modicum of benefit” to be obtained from CPR? In the light of the data on survival after CPR among patients with cancer, as well as what we know about our ability to reverse the course of this patient’s underlying illnesses, we are forced to conclude that her chances of surviving until discharge were virtually nonexistent and could not be improved by CPR. Furthermore, we can see that there are risks involved in performing CPR, including the development of a chronic vegetative state - which many believe is worse than death - or, more likely, survival after the initial resuscitation but with death occurring after an indefinite stay in the intensive care unit. This was what the house staff feared. For them the choice was clear: death on the oncology ward, surrounded by family members and the nurses and doctors who knew the patient well, versus death in the intensive care unit after multiple invasive, painful, and dehumanizing procedures. From the perspective of the patient and her family the choice was less clear. When asked to make their choice, they were not well informed about the likely outcome of CPR. They had never been in an intensive care unit or seen a respirator. For them the choice appeared to be between a chance of life and certain death. When they chose CPR, they were actually choosing some-thing that did not exist - a chance for the patient to live.

            Problems like these are not easily solved. Sometimes all that is required is more information about the choices involved. At other times, for a variety of reasons, including guilt and unrealistic hopes for a medical miracle, patients or their families continue to request CPR even when it would clearly be futile. In cases like these, in which CPR offers no conceivable benefit and much possible harm, I believe that patient autonomy cannot be our only guide. The principle of autonomy, which allows patients to refuse any procedure or choose among different beneficial procedures, does not allow them to demand nonbeneficial and potentially harmful procedures. On the other hand, if patients continue to request CPR even after being in-formed of its futility, can we justify the use of CPR on the basis of compassion, the desire not to desert our often desperate patients? Although there may be times when we use CPR for this purpose, we should recognize the patient’s impassioned plea for a form of therapy that he or she knows to be futile for what it is - a cry for help, an acute expression of the dying patient’s distress at his or her condition. There are usually bet-ter ways to deal with this distress than offering CPR as a sort of high-technology placebo; these include listening to the patient’s hopes and fears, reassuring him or her that the doctors will continue to be there and pro-vide appropriate therapy, and if necessary, referring the patient to psychiatric personnel or clergy trained to help patients who are dying.

            A closer look at this problem, however, shows us that it is usually not simply a case of a patient demanding something. The young woman with leukemia and her family, for example, were in fact offered a choice between CPR and no CPR. Why did the physicians involved even consider CPR an option? What purpose was served by offering the patient a treatment that was known to be of no benefit? If it was done to preserve the patient’s autonomy, her autonomy still did not extend to choosing useless procedures. If it was done to relieve her family of guilt, so that they could rest assured that they had really done everything, that purpose could have been better achieved by having the doctors assure the family that every-thing had been and was being done and that CPR would not add to the therapy. If it was offered to give the family hope, then it was a cruel hope indeed - not only a false hope but a hope that led them to make decisions that could only increase the patient’s suffering. Since we were offering her not the chance to survive until discharge but the chance to survive for a couple of days or weeks in the intensive care unit - intubated and sedated and with an arterial line, central line, Foley catheter, and nasogastric tube in place - the choice should have been presented as such, if it had to be presented at all. I believe that the choice should not have been offered. Offering CPR to this patient represented bad faith because doing so implied a potential for benefit when there was none.

            What I suggest is a different way of using CPR that takes into account not only the patient’s autonomy but also the physician’s responsibility to provide care consonant with medical reality. In cases in which CPR has been shown to be of no benefit, as in patients with metastatic cancer, it should not be considered an alter-native and should not be presented as such. In these cases physicians could write DNR orders on the chart, with the following type of documentation: “This patient has a condition for which CPR has been shown not to be effective. In case of cardiopulmonary arrest, CPR should not be performed.” Because there is a potential for misuse, the type of diagnosis for which such an order could be written should be strictly limited to those for which there is clear documentation of the ineffectiveness of CPR. Consensus needs to be reached, probably on the national level, about what those diagnoses are.

            Many cases will not be so clear. Patients with some chronic diseases, such as renal failure, have long-term survival rates after CPR that are low (usually less than 5 percent) but real. In such cases, patient autonomy is the overriding principle and informed consent for CPR should be obtained. Physicians should be strongly encouraged to discuss the preferences of their chronically ill patients with them. The discussions should include the provision of information about the chances of survival after CPR and the risks involved. If a patient’s preferences have not been ascertained before cardiac arrest (and it is our responsibility as physicians to see that this seldom happens), CPR should be initiated and continued until the patient’s wishes can be ascertained.

            Patients who have a cardiac arrest as a result of an acute insult, such as a drug overdose, a complication of a procedure or anesthesia, or an acute myocardial infarction, make up a third category. They are the patients for whom CPR was originally designed and the patients in whom it is most frequently successful. There is usually no question about the appropriateness of CPR in these patients, and CPR should be initiated unless the patient has previously expressed a desire not to have such treatment.

            CPR is a desperate technique that works relatively infrequently, and in many types of patients, virtually never. To solve the ethical dilemmas posed by CPR we must first face that medical fact. Furthermore, as we have seen, there is potential harm in CPR in that patients may be kept alive for days to weeks undergoing painful and dehumanizing procedures with no conceivable medical benefits. Because of these facts, we need to reevaluate the ways we use CPR. Too often CPR just happens, without inquiry into the patient’s wishes or consideration of its chances of success. Both patient autonomy and physician responsibility are important factors in making decisions regarding CPR. In cases in which CPR has any potential for success, the principle of patient autonomy dictates the patient’s right to choose or refuse such treatment. In order for patients to exercise this right, however, two conditions must be met. First, patients need to be given sufficient information concerning the likely outcome of CPR and the risks involved, so that an informed decision can be made. Second, because CPR is attempted unless patients have been asked whether they wish it and have refused it, physicians need to involve their patients earlier and more frequently in the decision to use CPR.

            The issue of patient autonomy is irrelevant, however, when CPR has no potential benefit. Here, the physician’s duty to provide responsible medical care precludes CPR, either as a routine process in the absence of a decision by a patient or as a response to a patient’s misguided request for such treatment in the absence of adequate information. In such cases it is not the physician’s responsibility to offer CPR. Both physicians and patients must come to terms with the inability of medicine to postpone death indefinitely.

720 Harrison Ave. Boston, MA 02118

LESLIE J. BLACKHALL, M.D.


REFERENCES

1. Kouwenhoven WB, Jude JR, Knickerbocker GG. Closed-chest cardiac massage. JAMA 1960; 173:1064-7.

2. Talbott JH. Introduction. Jude JR, Elam JO. Fundamentals of cardiopulmonary resuscitation. Philadelphia: F.A. Davis, 1965.

3. Bedell SE, Delbanco TL. Choices about cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the hospital: When do physicians talk with patients? N Engl J Med 1984; 310:1089-93.

4. Charlson ME, Sax FL, MacKenzie R, Fields SD, Braham RL, Douglas RG Jr. Resuscitation: How do we decide? A prospective study of physicians’ preferences and the clinical course of hospitalized patients. JAMA 1986; 255:1316-22.

5. Youngner SJ, Lewandowski W, McClish DK, Juknialis BW, Coulton C, Bartlett ET. ‘Do not resuscitate’ orders: incidence and implications in a medical intensive care unit. JAMA 1985; 253:54-7.

6. Evans AL, Brody BA. The do-not-resuscitate order in teaching hospitals. JAMA 1985; 253:2236-9.

7. Bedell SE, Pelle D, Maher PL, Cleary PD. Do-not-resuscitate orders for critically ill patients in the hospital: How are they used and what is their impact? JAMA 1986; 256:233-7.

8. Brett AS, McCullough LB. When patients request specific interventions: defining the limits of the physician’s obligation. N Engl J Med 1986; 315:1347-51.

9. Gulati RS, Bhan GL, Horan MA. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation of old people. Lancet 1983; 2:267-9.

10. SE, Delbanco TL, Cook EF, Epstein FH. Survival after cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the hospital. N Engl J Med 1983; 309: 569-76.

11. Peatfield RC, Sillett RW, Taylor D, McNicol MW. Survival after cardiac arrest in hospital. Lancet 1977; 1:1223-5.

12. Hershy CO, Fisher L. Why outcome of cardiopulmonary resuscitation on general wards is so poor. Lancet 1982; 1:31-4.

13. Johnson AL, Tanser PH, Ulan RA, Wood TE. Results of cardiac resuscitation in 552 patients. Am J Card 1967; 20:831-5.

14. Fiisgen I, Summa J-D. How much sense is there in an attempt to resuscitate an aged person? Gerontology 1978; 24:37-45.

15. Messert B, Quaglieri CE. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation: perspectives and problems. Lancet 1976; 2:410-2.

16. Scott RPF. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation in a teaching hospital: a survey of cardiac arrests occurring outside intensive care units and emergency rooms. Anaesthesia 1981; 36:526-30.

17. Hollingsworth JH. The results of cardiopulmonary resuscitation: a 3-yearuniversity hospital experience. Ann Intern Med 1969; 71:459-66.

18. Castagna J, Weil MH, Shubin H. Factors determining survival in patients with cardiac arrest. Chest 1974; 65:527-9.

19. Camarata SJ, Weil MH, Hanashiro PK, Shubin H. Cardiac arrest in the critically ill. I. A study of predisposing causes in 132 patients. Circulation 1971; 44:688-95.

20. DeBard ML. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation: analysis of six years’ experience and review of the literature. Ann Emerg Med 1981; 10:408-16.

21. Lemire JG, Johnson AL. Is cardiac resuscitation worthwhile? A decade of experience. N EngIJ Med 1972;286:970-2.


 

 

 


Note that the statistics on survival to discharge after in-hospital CPR have not changed significantly since the publication of this article in 1986:

[1] “Cardiopulmonary resuscitation in intensive care unit and non-intensive care unit patients. Immediate and long-term survival.” Karetzky. M., Arch Intern Med, June 26 1995; 155(12), 1277-80.

[2] “Efficacy of CPR in a general, adult ICU,” Myrianthefs P., Resuscitation, April, 2003; 57(1):43-8.

[3] “Epidemiologic Study of In-Hospital Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation in the Elderly”, Ehlenbach, W., N Engl J Med , July 2, 2009; 361:22-31.

 


 

xcxxcxxc  F ” “

 xxxx» cont